Symposium Introduction

Avatar

Response

A Yawning Chasm Not Easily Closed

I think this is really an exciting piece of work. Being very well-researched and groundbreaking in its use of materials from the von Balthasar archive, it brings a fresh perspective to our understanding of Karl Barth and of his relationship with his close Catholic friend. I learned a lot I didn’t know from reading it. I am happy to recommend this book highly, though I have reservations about a few of its lesser arguments.

First, a small but not unimportant point about how to translate a particular phrase. Long regularly comes back to a remark made by Barth in the first volume of his Church Dogmatics. Barth is trying to get a handle on what it is that finally separates the Roman Catholic church from the churches of the Reformation. When God’s Word is proclaimed, he asks, is Christ’s action tied to the ecclesiastical office of the minister, or is it actually the other way around, namely, that the office is tied to Christ’s action whenever the Word is “actualized,” or “made effectual,” through preaching? The first would be the Catholic view, while the second would be the Reformation’s.

Barth wants to insist with the Reformation that the saving efficacy of the church’s ministry resides in Christ alone, who bears witness to himself through the preaching of the church. The saving efficacy of preaching is not divided between Christ and the minister, along the lines, say, of primary and secondary causality. Causality thinking, Barth contends, is out of place when it comes to understanding the mystery of divine and human action. For Barth, there is only one Saving Agent, and his name is Jesus Christ. When others act in and through Christ as his instruments and witnesses, they acquire no secondary saving agency of their own. No matter if there is more than one acting subject, there is always only one Saving Agent. The issue can then be rephrased: Is there only one Saving Agent at work in the ministry of the church, or are there many lesser ones alongside the One who is supreme? Barth observes: “From the standpoint of our theses this question is the puzzling cleft which has cut right across the church during the last 400 years” (I/1, 99).

Long regularly re-translates the German in Barth’s observation—der rätselhafte Riß—as “the enigmatic cleft.” The author resorts to other variants as well, but this is the one he prefers. However, the phrase might better be rendered as “the perplexing rift” or “the vexing split.” The noun der Riß has connotations of “rupture” more nearly than of “cleft.” Barth is pointing to a conception of human action in relation to God’s grace that has torn the fabric of the church for more than 400 years. While the translation problem is minor, the issue to which it points is not. I will return to it in due course.

At the heart of Long’s book is a contrast between a form of “neoscholastic retrenchment” in Roman Catholic theology as over against a “modernizing” or “post-metaphysical” movement in Protestant circles that would claim Barth as their supposed forebear. The neoscholastics are critical of Balthasar for being too influenced by Barth while the post-metaphysical claimants seem to confirm their deepest fears about where Barth goes wrong. Although Long overstates the influence of these two groupings—I don’t think their combined forces have led to the “collapse” of Balthasar’s interpretation of Barth—they have at least put a dent in it. Long is right to worry that they are having a baleful influence on a younger generation of scholars, and more importantly that they create unfortunate and finally specious obstacles to the future of ecumenical rapprochement.

I want to concentrate on Long’s critique of those Protestants who would argue that Barth is a “post-metaphysical” theologian, at least by implication, because he is alleged to be “thoroughly modern.” I agree with Long that, among other things, this line of interpretation overstates the degree to which Barth was influenced by Kant. Barth’s theology arguably includes “modern,” “post-modern,” and even “pre-modern” elements all at once. It would be better to characterize his theology as “thoroughly eclectic.” Only by being happily eclectic could Barth proceed with his project of trying to take every thought captive in obedience to Christ without becoming a captive to modernity himself.

Long singles out six features in the new “post-metaphysical” Barth interpretation, which if adopted would “radically revise the Christian doctrine of God” (148).

    • First, if an attempt is made (as it is) to identify the Son’s obedience to the Father in the economy with his generation by the Father in eternity, wouldn’t that make creation intrinsic to the God’s being?
    • Second, is there really (as claimed) no prior and permanent role for the Logos asarkos in the eternal being of the triune God? If enfleshment belongs eternally to the Son’s essence, how would the Son be free to become incarnate? “Has not flesh conditioned God’s triunity?” (148).
    • Third, if the divine missions in the economy are necessary to the Trinity’s eternal processions, wouldn’t this mean that God cannot be God without the creation? Indeed, wouldn’t it mean that the distinction between the economic and the immanent Trinity is collapsed?
    • Fourth, if God becomes the Holy Trinity through his pre-temporal act of election, wouldn’t that again mean that God cannot be God without the creation?
    • Fifth, doesn’t this view make God to be fundamentally dependent on the creation? Wouldn’t God and the world mutually condition one another?
    • Finally, doesn’t this view entail that divine predications like simplicity and impassibility must be jettisoned? Wouldn’t it introduce an element of potentiality into God’s being so that God would no longer be actus purus?

In short, “if the processions and missions must be held together as an eternal act, then not only the Son’s humanity but all of creation would need to be eternal” (149). As Long rightly observes, the later Barth repeatedly blocks such moves as we find in this line of Barth interpretation. Long rightly quotes Barth: “In the inner life of God, as the eternal essence of the Father, Son and Holy Ghost, the divine essence does not of course, need any actualization” (IV/2, 113). This is far from an isolated remark. For the Barth of Church Dogmatics, from beginning to end, God does not need the world in order to be God, nor is there any element of contingency in God’s being.

Long is also correct when he appeals to Aquinas for whom the “missions” are not eternal, because Aquinas posited that it was possible for God to do something temporally that did not require God to actualize a potential. This is Barth’s view as well. For Barth as for Aquinas, “creation does not add something to, or take away from, God” (149), i.e., to God’s eternal essence.

Like Aquinas, Barth always affirmed that God’s triune being was pure act, that it was perfect and sufficient in itself, and that it did not exclude a distinction between God’s “absolute being” and his “contingent will” (III/1, 15). Barth openly aligned himself with the medieval Dominican in this regard. He noted that Aquinas upheld “the most important statement in the doctrine of creation—namely, that of the novitas mundi [contingency of the world]” (III/1, 4 rev.). Barth also endorsed Aquinas’s teaching “that the world is not eternal but has a beginning.” He agreed with him that the idea of creation’s contingency “is only credibile, non autem scibile et demonstrabile [a matter of belief, not of immediate knowledge or rational demonstration] (S. theol., I, qu. 46, art. 2c)” (III/1, 4). On all such matters the actually existing textual Barth is far closer to Aquinas than to Hegel and the Barth revisionists.

The revisionist line of Barth interpretation that Long challenges can only maintain itself by ignoring a great deal of contrary textual evidence. It attempts to do so mainly by claiming that the later Barth is “inconsistent.” On those grounds, it proceeds as if all contrary textual evidence in the Church Dogmatics can simply be brushed aside. These are complicated questions that cannot be pursued here. I deal with them extensively, however, in my forthcoming book Reading Barth with Charity: A Hermeneutical Proposal (Baker Academic, 2015). For the time being I would simply like to align myself with the line of questioning that Stephen Long so trenchantly sets forth.

In conclusion, I want to turn to a matter touched on at the outset. Professor Long admirably wants to look for ways in which the historic divisions between Roman Catholic theology and Protestant theology can be overcome. One of the neuralgic points to which he returns throughout his book is the question of whether the church can properly be described as a “prolongation of the incarnation.” This is one of the deepest differences that Long identifies as separating Balthasar and Barth (285–86). For Balthasar if the church is not the prolongation of the incarnation, there is no historical drama of God’s actions through the church (no “theodrama”) (230). For Barth, who rejected this idea as “blasphemy” (IV/3, 729), it illicitly elevates the church to the point where it not only acts alongside Christ, but in practice even above him “as his vicar in earthly history” (IV/3, 36). The only proper view for Barth was one where the church was always completely subordinate to Christ, never alongside or above him. The church was always in the position of an absolute dependence on grace, which for Barth meant the position of prayer.

The intractability of this issue is only intensified when it is recognized, as Long notes, that in Lumen Gentium the church is still referred to as the extension of the incarnation (216 n.123). Long can’t understand why Barth refuses to follow Balthasar on this question. He implies that he himself agrees with Balthasar in holding that Barth fails to have “an adequate account of human agency” (230).

It is, however, tendentious to accuse Barth’s view of being “inadequate” without probing into the deeper issues. What counts as “adequate” is precisely what is contested between Catholicism and the Reformation. Balthasar strives heroically to construct a view of the incarnatus prolongatus that would escape from many of the Reformation’s objections. (219). He cannot escape, however, from upholding the idea that human actors can play some auxiliary causal or contributory role, apart from and alongside Christ, in carrying out the work of salvation. This observation pertains especially to Balthasar’s view of Mary and the ordained ministry of the church (presbyters, bishops, and the pope).

Balthasar cannot strictly uphold the Reformation’s fundamental conviction that human salvation occurs sola fide, sola gratia, and solus Christus. There is a yawning chasm between the idea of “Christ alone” and that of “Christ primarily.” For Barth and the Reformation, the faithful actions of human beings give them the status of being “witnesses,” and even “mediators,” but without ever making them into secondary “Saving Agents,” which could only mean their usurping of the incommunicable office and inviolable dignity of the Lord Jesus Christ. For Barth and the Reformation, everything believers may do is at its best an act of gratitude, never one with any claim to “merit” before God. Barth’s view might not convince Balthasar and his contemporary adherents, but it should not be perplexing as to why he holds it. For him, the church is always a witness to the incarnation, never in any sense an extension of it.

Divine and human action are, as I argue in How to Read Karl Barth (Oxford, 1991), always related for Barth by means of the Chalcedonian Pattern. They are related “without separation or division” (inseparable unity), “without confusion or change” (abiding distinction), and with an “asymmetrical ordering principle” (the absolute primacy and precedence belong always to God). Within this fundamental structure divine and human agency are non-competitive. For Barth in line with the Reformation, Catholic views of divine and human agency regularly violate the stricture against confusion or change, and especially against compromising the principle of asymmetry.

  • D. Stephen Long

    D. Stephen Long

    Reply

    Response to George Hunsinger

    I am deeply grateful to George Hunsinger for his review of my book, and for the many contributions he made to it through his own work. It will come as no surprise to our readers that he agrees with my critique of the postmetaphysical Barthians. Much of my critique echoes his. On the whole he and I do not disagree on any substantial descriptive or interpretive matters. I am pleased he thinks I am correct that the postmetaphysical Barthians overstate the influence of Kant on Barth. He likewise recognizes how that overstatement plays into the hands of some Roman Catholic theologians who claim Roman Catholicism alone protects reason from the historicizing fideism of modernity and Protestantism (See Matthew Rose’s “Karl Barth’s Failures” in First Things for another familiar version of this narrative. One goal I had in this book is to at least problematize that familiar narrative). If Barth is the modern Kantian some assume he is, that version of Catholic theology has warrant for its judgment that Barth failed to deliver theology from modernity (wrongly assuming, of course, that modern historicism and Medieval metaphysics must be set in opposition as the Thomists of the strict observance do in a very modern gesture.) I am also pleased that Dr. Hunsinger finds the convenientia between Aquinas and Barth that I find convincing. Perhaps Dr. McCormack is moving in that direction as well, given his essay in Thomas Aquinas and Karl Barth: An Unofficial Catholic-Protestant Dialogue. That important book was not available to me when I was working on Saving Karl Barth. If I have interpreted Dr. McCormack correctly, it would require me to nuance some of my criticisms. One criticism Dr. Hunsinger makes of my interpretive work is that I overstated the collapse of Balthasar’s interpretation among Barthian theologians. He suggests it still has significant traction. The positive assessment my defense of Balthasar’s reading has garnered among some of them suggests he is right.

    The significant issue between us is not primarily interpretive but evaluative, although the two cannot be decisively separated. Dr. Hunsinger points to the phrase der rätselhafte Riß and its interpretation as key. The statement appears in Church Dogmatics I.1 and forms the basis for Balthasar’s engagement with Barth’s theology. The “puzzling rupture” between Catholics and Protestants, Barth and Hunsinger suggest, is a question of the relation between divine and human agency. Here is how Barth puts it, “Is Christ’s action, real proclamation, the Word of God preached, tied to the ecclesiastical office and consequently to a human act, or conversely, as one might conclude from this oret are the office and act tied to the action of Christ, to the actualizing of proclamation by God, to the Word of God preached? From the standpoint of our theses this question is the puzzling cleft which has cut right across the church during the last 400 years.” I cite the passage on page 242, and suggest that it does not fit well Barth’s affirmation of Reformed preaching if Barth distinguishes the Divine act from the human act. I stated, “Barth sets Jesus’ role over and against the church, rather than within it, which does not fit seamlessly with his previous argument that the Word and proclaimer are one, not two.” Here we may have a disagreement in our interpretation of Barth.

    Before Barth uses the term “der rätselhafte Riß,” he makes a surprising turn. He admonishes his reader not to side with Harnack and take offense at the Catholic teaching that the bishop can be vicarius Chrisi. Barth writes, “One can neither estimate the Roman Catholic position correctly nor take up the correct Evangelical position if (with Harnack, op. cit., 446) one takes offence already at the idea of vicariate or succession. One would have to deny Christus praesens to deny in principle the vicarius Christi. The difference between Roman Catholic dogmatics and ourselves, which, of course, we must always keep in view, cannot refer to the fact of this vicariate or succession, but only to its manner” (CD I.1, 97). I find it fascinating that Barth affirms the possibility that because of Christ’s presence to his church, the vicarius Christi should not a priori be denied. What he then rejects about Roman Catholicism is that it “dehumanizes” the bishop in order to affirm the vicarius Christi. Does that not suggest the possibility that Christ’s presence makes possible the bishop as the vicar of Christ in his humanity? I interpret Barth as suggesting this possibility. Notice that in the quotation Hunsinger points to, Barth does not explicitly reject the “human act.”  He asks if “institution and act” are tied to Christ’s act. He has a role for the human act, but not if it is the condition for the Divine act. If that interpretation is correct, then Balthasar would be incorrect when he faults Barth for failing to have an adequate account of human agency. Dr. Hunsinger thinks I have sided with Balthasar in attributing such a failure to Barth. His interpretation is understandable but not quite right. I think Barth demonstrated he had a more robust account of human agency in the realm of grace than Balthasar and perhaps Hunsinger suggest. It will come to flourish in Barth’s remarkable question in his Doctrine of Reconciliation, “Is it really the case that He has caused His Word to become flesh not merely in order that He may be an act for us in His own person, but in order that we may also be an act for Him?” (CD 4.2 791). Barth assumes the answer is yes. The only way to make sense of such a claim without falling into the silliness of a process metaphysics or some of the revisionary metaphysics Barthians are setting forth today would be to affirm secondary causality in which we acknowledge God’s “primary causality” is never in competition with it. So my argument is that Barth did have a strong account of human agency even in the mediation of grace and this is found in the unity of Divine Word and the preacher in proclamation, a unity that does not reject the humanity of the preacher. It is a unity because these two forms of causality are never in competition. My critique of Barth then was this: “He [Barth] denies to the Catholic Eucharist what he affirms for Reformed preaching” (242).

    I do not think what I just stated disagrees with Dr. Hunsinger’s statement:

    “The only proper view for Barth was one where the church was always completely subordinate to Christ, never alongside or above him. The church was always in the position of an absolute dependence on grace, which for Barth meant the position of prayer.”

    All theologians should affirm this. Do Catholics deny it? Yves Congar makes a great deal of the importance of the prayer that begins the Mass: “the Lord be with you—and with your spirit.” It suggests that even though all is in good order with the office and institution, unless there is a prayer for the Spirit, “the Lord,” everything remains ineffectual. The Mass is not a technology that dispenses grace; it is a prayer. If this is the case, then the “rupture” is all the more puzzling. We remain unsure what divides us. Barth’s criticism of Catholicism could be construed as a charge that it is a kind of gnosticizing where the human materiality of the priest, like the materiality of the bread and wine, have to be evacuated for Divine agency to work. If so, then it would be Barth who affirmed a more Medieval and patristic outlook in which Divine and human agency become one without divinity ceasing to be divinity or humanity humanity.

    Balthasar picks up on Barth’s expression “der rätselhafte Riß” because he sees in it a “crack,” or opening, for a Catholic-Protestant conversation. It is the reason he titles the first chapter of his Barth book, “Zerrissene Kirche.” If the rupture is fully intelligible on either side, then there is no need for a conversation. Conversion of one side to the other is the only way forward; all other approaches are closed. If the rupture is “puzzling,” then an opening exists. We do not yet know if the rupture is irremediable because we remain uncertain as to what and why it is. Hunsinger is also correct that the disagreement between us is related to the question whether the church should be spoken of as the extension of the Incarnation. Because Joseph Mangina will raise a similar concern in his review, I will address that important question at that point.

Avatar

Response

To Trust the Person Who Wrote the Books

The thesis of this book is that von Balthasar spotted that when Karl Barth criticized the Catholic idea of an analogy of being between creatures and God, he had confused the Catholic analogia entis with the doctrine of a “pure nature,” used by Tridentine Catholic theologians to theorize a virtual reality which is emptied of grace. Long’s thesis is that von Balthasar thought that when Karl Barth heard “analogy of being between creatures and God” the word “creatures” got itself translated into “pure nature” and so Barth imagined that Catholics were constructing a real (rather than hypothetical) foundation for theology upon this “pure nature,” which is graceless and Godless. Long observes that von Balthasar has not only this negative observation about Barth to contribute, but also a positive perception of a “turn” toward acknowledgement of the “analogy” made by Barth round about the time he wrote his book on Anselm, and which is apparent in the Church Dogmatics. Barth may prefer to call it “analogy of faith” rather than “analogy of being,” but in effect he has perceived that, in the person of Christ, there is an analogy between creature (created human nature) and God (uncreated divine nature), and that this analogy is the operative center of theology. Long’s thesis is, moreover, that von Balthasar was right about this, and not merely right about that as a textual claim with regard to Barth’s writings, but right about reality—there is a Christ-formed analogy of being between creatures and God, and above all there is no non-hypothetically, actually existent pure nature.

As Long notes, von Balthasar appeared on the Basel scene quite early, towing a volume of the Dogmatics around in his briefcase “like a puppy” (Barth’s words). Maybe, and Long encourages the supposition, there was something Heisenbergian going on here, not in the Walter White sense of the production of crystal meth in the back of an old Volkswagen, but in the sense of the observer affecting the data, and the Swiss Jesuit’s perception of the Reformed pastor influencing Barth’s own theological trajectory. (You cannot be too careful around members of the Society of Jesus). Saving Karl Barth uses history and biography as its material for theology. He shows how, for instance, von Balthasar’s presence at Barth’s seminar on the Council of Trent, and its influence on his conception of Baptism, in its turn affected Barth’s later ideas about the “sacrament of faith.” The book is full of interesting details about the decades-long conversation between Barth and von Balthasar. The simpler version of the thesis of the book is that this conversation was valuable because it encouraged Barth to move toward analogy and encouraged von Balthasar to allow Christ to condition every facet of his theology. The affective heart of the book is the defense of the proposition that Protestant and Catholic theologies bear most fruit in dialogue with one another. The issue within which this desire for ecumenical dialogue is elaborated is that of pure nature versus “always already graced by Christ nature.”

Long defends this thesis against two kinds of critics. On the one hand, there are Protestant theologians who think that von Balthasar’s interpretation of Barth is flawed. Barth never, according to Bruce McCormack, simply turned from being a dialectical theologian who denied analogy between God and creatures, to being a theologian of analogy. McCormack claimed in his biography of the Swiss theologian that Barth continuously maintains a dialectic of “veiling and unveiling,” throughout the Church Dogmatics. On this historical reading of Barth’s development, he makes no decisive turn from dialectical theology to a theology that assumes analogy between God and creatures. Plus, as McCormack has it, von Balthasar fails to note the real decisive new step that Barth takes in Church Dogmatics II.ii, when he puts the “election” of Christ at the center of his theology. McCormack first set forth this claim in volume one of his Barth biography. Instead of writing volumes two or three , he went on to write systematic, theological works in which he drew out the implications of this “Barthian evaluation” of election. The theological proposal which McCormack’s reading of Barth on election elicits is that God’s eternal act of electing humanity in Christ entails that God has eternally bound himself to humanity in Christ—and thus that God’s act of “electing” the Word bound God to become Incarnate. Or, again, to put that in crude terms, one kind of critic of his thesis is “too Protestant” to accept von Balthasar’s salvaging of Barth’s tendency toward a Christological analogy of being. Instead of Christic analogy and Incarnation, McCormack presents election, event, and opposition to traditional metaphysics as the central lesson to be learned from Barth’s theology. Especially in its apparent eschewal of metaphysics, that pushes Barth (and Protestant theology) too far into, as it were, a Protestant extreme, for Catholics to have anything much to say to Protestants.

On the other hand, there are those whom Long calls Ressourcement Thomists, who criticize von Balthasar for his lack of metaphysics. These in effect defend the idea of pure nature, claiming that theology is impossible without a foundation in “nature,” in a pre-theological or non-theological sense of the term “nature.” Those who promote this criticism of von Balthasar are Catholics, and were their opinion to prevail it would push Catholic theology too far into, as it were, hard Catholicism, for Protestants to have much of anything to say to Catholics. We learn about two Catholic critics of von Balthasar’s treatment of nature, pure and applied (graced). One is clearly Saving Karl Barth’s good cop; the Dominican Thomas Joseph White is presented throughout as a thoughtful and open-minded theological critic of von Balthasar’s failure to give “nature” its due. Whatever he thinks about the principle of non-contradiction, it must be annoying for a theologian to coexist at one and the same time, if in different places, with another thinker who has with diametrically opposed opinions and yet nearly the same name as himself. Steven A. Long takes the role, in this book, of the bad cop, indeed, one has to say the poor theologian, who confuses the councils of Nicaea and Chalcedon and defends the real existence of pure nature on purely political grounds. As quoted in Saving Karl Barth, Long explicitly defends the necessity of a doctrine of pure nature on the grounds that, without it, it is impossible to argue for public prayer in schools, or for any other accoutrements of Christian influence on the secular State. Another figure who creeps from time to time into this narrative is the old, anti-Ressourcement Thomist, Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange. Saving Karl Barth is too polite to mention Garrigou’s own political engagements, as expressed for example in his use of Vichy Radio to promote French anti-Semitism in 1941 or his production of an introduction to an edition of Thomas Aquinas’ De Regimen Principe just a few months before the condemnation of the Action Francaise in 1926. The proximity of “pure naturism” to monarchism and Gallicanism (or in our own context, Americanism) still calls for further exploration. Even without mentioning these embarrassing episodes, Saving Karl Barth gives us a whiff of what Garrigou’s theology smells like, in a state of nature. Garrigou and his kind were influenced by similar political concerns to those that, according to this book, motivate Long. But not White: Long treats White’s defense of a philosophy of nature with respect. It is very tempting for those who don’t think an actual (as opposed to hypothetical) state of pure nature exists to regard their opponents through reductionist filters, and to say, for instance, “it’s all about reducing theology to politics.” Long’s polite and conversational mode with respect to Thomas Joseph White shows that this temptation can and must be withstood.

What I like most about this book is the way it shows that both the post-Metaphysical, “extreme Protestant” and Ressourcement Thomist, hard-Catholic, depersonalize theology. Theologians are persons, and books express their author’s personality. And yet, by ignoring statements which Barth made about his own development—such as that von Balthasar was right about locating his theological maturation in the Anselm book, or what Barth himself said about analogy and its place in theology, and what he did not say about election, and how it could be a principle which actively defines who God is—McCormack bypasses the person of the author, wresting his texts away from their source of life and creator. Does the person of the author have a deciding say in the meaning of his writings? Long repeatedly “trounces” McCormack on points of logic, leaving me wondering if, however illogical McCormack’s position, it might not be Barth’s own. But within a page or so Long will back that up by showing how the “extreme Protestant” reading of Barth, which so centralizes the “election” of humanity in Christ as to give Christ an eternal human nature bound for Incarnation, is at odds with Barth’s own texts. Likewise, the hard Catholic who wants to replace what he or she sees as an excess emphasis on grace with a “re-sourcement of nature,” is interested in a metaphysics of nature, not of persons. Persons are not the most fundamental and “hardest” feature in the metaphysical landscape of “hard Catholicism.” That seems to indicate that the Incarnation of divine and human nature in the single person of Christ, and the three divine persons of the Trinity are not the deepest inspiration of the Catholic “return to metaphysics.”

So what I thought was best in this book, with its rather devastating critiques of Steve A. Long and Bruce McCormack, was its defense of “personalism.” The author might fault me for this, and want to say it is the person of Christ who is at the center: it is the person of Christ who makes the marriage of the two, divine and human, natures possible, not the existence of “natures” in a raw, ungraced state (A. Long), or even that of persons. I would say that that theological point is absolutely true, and this is what has, over the centuries, made the person the subject of ever-deeper philosophical and metaphysical investigation. To me, where both of the author’s “extremes” meet is not so much in lack of enthusiasm for ecumenism as in antipersonalism. But, of course, I too have a personal stake in this: Bruce McCormack’s biography was a huge inspiration to me when it first appeared, because it made me realize that biography and history can be the material of theology. It made me write a (much less good) biography, and the writing of which cured me forever of formalism; writing it made me realize that in order to understand a writer’s books one must trust the writer himself, the person who wrote the books. Biography is not a matter of romantic identification with the author, but of trusting him or her as one trusts another person. This became my own hermeneutic, and it is clearly the hermeneutic that guides Saving Karl Barth. Without such a “personalist” hermeneutic, one can cite Barth against McCormack until one is blue in the face, and the reply will be, simply, that the author is not the best judge of his own work, does not know, for instance, whether or not he turned to analogy in 1932. Long will still have in hand logical criticisms of McCormack’s position, and very powerful ones too, but this will be the only evidence he can call in, without the assumption that a personalist hermeneutic is the one which makes best sense of an author’s work. The three of us (Murphy, Long, and McCormack) have written theological books whose material is history and biography: is there anything to learn here about theological method? Long clearly thinks so. He notes the significance of the St. John communities, set up by von Balthasar and Adrienne von Speyr, which still exist, as a flesh-and-blood, existential “hermeneutic” of von Balthasar’s writings, and observes that Barth’s writings, by contrast, have been propounded by a Protestant “elite.”

For me, Saving Karl Barth was a very exciting book. Von Balthasar’s book about Barth was composed at exactly the time when Henri de Lubac’s criticisms of the doctrine of pure, ungraced, nature were becoming known, and, in their turn, criticized by important figures in the Roman Curia such as Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange. It was published just a year or so after de Lubac was silenced by the Jesuits (not by Rome; no Dominicans were involved in his silencing). I’ve always thought that von Balthasar’s book about Barth was in some way a contribution to this debate but I’ve never been able to put my finger on how. Saving Karl Barth explains how, repeating the mantra about Barth’s mistranslating analogia entis into “pure nature” umpteen times until it had first got itself into my thick skull and then went round and round inside it like a pop song which gets stuck on a repeat loop in one’s memory. The book could easily have shed fifty pages and been quite perfect. The reiterations certainly help to hammer home a difficult thesis in the early stages of the book, but eventually they become wearisome. People will skim through parts of the book and that’s a shame because it has a gem at its heart.

The only objection I can find to the content of the book is that the author says that von Balthasar disagreed with Vatican II. He is making a strategic gesture here: he wants to say that post-Vatican II liberal Catholicism played to Barth’s fears, by seeming to resort to yet another worldly foundation, of welfare and philanthropy. All of it was done in a “nice” way, not the hard way of the Thomists, but it nonetheless permitted a “pure,” graceless and Christless nature to condition Catholic theology. In her book on Culture and the Thomist Tradition, Tracey Rowland ascribed such a view of Vatican II to Ratzinger and von Balthasar. But, as Larry Chapp pointed out at the time, in Nova et Vetera (Winter, 2005), von Balthasar never criticized the texts of Vatican II: he thought the problems of the post-Vatican II Church were due to the worldliness of our Bishops, not the Conciliar texts. Long’s book has a really good grasp on the texts of von Balthasar and Barth, and this is the only time, so far as I can see, that he slips up on either of them. He doesn’t give any textual support for the broad claim that von Balthasar objected to Vatican II. There may be one or two places where he criticizes spots in certain texts (he thought Lumen Gentium underplayed Mary’s personality), but, as Long shows here, von Balthasar thought Trent does not have the last word in everything: no responsible author would say that von Balthasar “disagreed with Trent.”

But these are very minor criticisms. This is a tremendous book that will have a role in future Catholic and Protestant conversations about Thomas Aquinas, Hans Urs von Balthasar, and the future of speculative theology.

  • D. Stephen Long

    D. Stephen Long

    Reply

    Response to Francesca Aran Murphy

    Murphy’s first two sentences speak to one of the reasons I wrote this book; it is what I hope will disturb our current interpretations of Barth. For Balthasar, Barth identified the wrong problem in Catholic Theology. It was not the analogia entis, but a doctrine of pure nature. If my book makes a contribution beyond the historical material about Barth and Balthasar’s friendship, I hope that this argument will gain a hearing among theologians. At the least, I hope it might generate controversy. Granted, there are only a few places where Balthasar makes this explicit, he nevertheless does do so as I think I demonstrate, and if he is correct about the misidentification in Barth’s theology, it could lead to new research that moves beyond the rather exhausting defenses and counters that Barth did or did not understand the analogia entis. The two arguments are related, but to relate them is to shift the terms of the debate. The debate is not about the analogia entis per se.

    As I tried to argue it is unclear Catholic theologians are in agreement as to what the analogia entis is and what metaphysical or dogmatic status it has in Catholic theology, so we Protestant observers should be granted some interpretive charity in out feeble attempts to discern why it has become a deep source of division. Perhaps the analogia entis is not one thing someone is either for or against? Perhaps it is a number of metaphysical positions one could adopt? If that is the case, then if it is coupled with a doctrine of pure nature it might just be, if not the antichrist, a Grand Inquisitor who gets to investigate Jesus to determine if the being to which he has come is appropriate to our finite understanding, a being with a purely natural end and the means to attain that end, one that not even Jesus can convert (Balthasar unlike many interpreters recognized the role of Dostoevsky in Barth’s early theology). Surely Catholic theologians will immediately insist this is not what the analogia entis is. I agree. But even Balthasar, toward the end of his life, raised the question if this is what in distorted fashion it could become (271, 276–77). We see it, I think, in a Catholic argument that says we Catholics deserve to rule others because we alone preserved nature and reason against the relativizing, historicizing acids of modernity. A correlate is that if we do not rule it is a form of oppression. Although I do find this argument present in modern Catholicism (and as much, if not more, on the “progressive” as the “traditionalist” side of the ongoing Catholic internecine battles), it is not Catholicism at its best. So Murphy is correct that I worry about this argument among the “Ressourcement Thomists.” (I used that term rather than the more familiar “Thomists of the strict observance” as an act of interpretive charity. It is the term used by this movement; the movement itself is quite minor and ineffectual at the moment.)

    Balthasar’s work is important to me as an alternative to this modern Catholic position. It means his work cannot be mapped on to the all too familiar binaries of progressive/traditionalist or liberal/conservative. I am confident what I wrote above would be contested by Catholic theologians. I wonder if Francesca, whose work I admire, and who it seems agrees with me in part, would find my fears misplaced? If not, then it also demonstrates a profound insight in Balthasar’s work, something he wrote in 1968 in response to Barth’s death:

    He looked around already in 1945 and saw what in the meantime many other ecumenically minded Christians learned to see: that the fronts today to a large extent pass straight through the churches. The critical line ran there, where the faith in Jesus Christ as the only mediator between God and men (1 Tim 2, 5) and, we explicitly add, personal love to him is maintained or abandoned. (276).

    If Balthasar was correct in 1968, then any theologian who is content to read only Barth or Balthasar, only Tillich or Rahner, only Reformed or Catholic theology has not discerned well our moment.

    Murphy is also correct that the issue is about metaphysics. Balthasar more so than Barth reminds us of this and so any discussion between them requires an engagement with the revisionary metaphysics found among some Barthians that historicizes being versus a putative traditional metaphysics that stresses nature over history. The argument is complex, but in part comes down to how one reads the deo deo uno versus the de deo trino in Aquinas. (The divisions are not Thomas’). Although I have grave reservations about much of John Milbank’s Christendom project, something I learned early from him was that this binary—history or metaphysics—is a modern invention that does not need to be (See his Beyond Secular Order, 184–88). Milbank learned it, I think, from reading Balthasar and Derrida under Rowan Williams. As Murphy reminds us God is not a story, but being is not found except in and as history. Thomas understood this with his teaching on actus purus.

    I am grateful for Murphy’s intervention in my reading of Balthasar on Vatican II. She is absolutely correct and I wish I could add a footnote to the work to make this explicit. Balthasar’s concerns were not about Vatican II, which he affirmed. They were about a certain Schleiermachian trajectory of it that led to a “blessing of culture” as if it did not need to be ordered to our supernatural end. It is almost as if the traditionalist position of pure nature he opposed prior to the Council found new life in the progressive position of a “transcendental anthropology” after the Council, which is another reason why that binary does not work.

    I received some significant push back by Protestant friends for my impressionist argument that Balthasar’s work finds a home in the St. John Communities whereas Barth’s is primarily housed among an academic “elite” arguing over the dates of when he converted to what. One friend reminded me that I should not forget his formative role in the Confessing Church. That is true but are there churches today who bear Barth’s work in the way that community bears Balthasar’s? I was struck in visiting the two archives in Basel how different they are. Barth’s is more of a library. Balthasar’s is more of a lay monastic community. I would like to be proven wrong about this distinction and I do not by any means intend to suggest that finding a home among the academic elite disqualifies theology. But if Barth is to be a “common doctor” of the church, which I hope he is, then it will have to be more than that.

    I readily acknowledge that my arguments above read Barth from Balthasar’s perspective. They approach Barth from the perspective of his concerns about the “sawdust Thomism” he studied and its inadequacies to present the dynamic Personal engagement of God with God’s creatures. Barth had little stake in Catholic debates about neoscholasaticism, and to all accounts seldom heard Balthasar’s critique. However, Balthasar developed a Catholic, Barthian theology as if Barth heard that critique, which is why I continue to find his work so interesting. The best heir to that tradition today may very well be Francesca Murphy.

    • Avatar

      Joeseph Mangina

      Reply

      Comment from Joseph Mangina

      Anne’s comment on “warmth” underscores a point I often make to my students, namely that ecumenical dialogue involves far more than just lining up doctrines and magisterial pronouncements on both sides, as it’s a matter of the lived experience of being Protestant, Catholic, Orthodox or what have you. I think I have some inkling of why a Catholic might fault Barth for lack of “warmth”—and yet on the other hand Barth’s extraordinary blend of intellectual discipline and affectivity was part of what drew me to him in the first place. In fact, my own dissertation was (sort of) a defense of KB against the charge of revelation positivism, a supposed inattentiveness to the person who *receives* God’s grace in Christ. This sort of accusation never made much sense to me, in so far as I can read parts of the Church Dogmatics and find myself moved to tears. But then again, Protestant “warmth” may not be Catholic “warmth.” We have a long way to go before we know how to factor matters like this into our ecumenical theology.

    • Anne Michelle Carpenter

      Anne Michelle Carpenter

      Reply

      Comment from Anne Carpenter

      If I may add a comment of my own, I want to say how delighted I am by this conversation. Francesca Murphy’s stress on person and personality, and on the “hardness” of them, has given “Saving Karl Barth” back to me as if it were brand new in my hands again. I had already thought it an important work, but now it has a new, vital texture. So, too, does the generous conversation between Murphy and D. Stephen Long here. It gestures toward an ecumenical theology borne by those taking part in the conversation, that is, carried along by personality perhaps even more richly than any words they might use.

      I studied under Steve at Marquette, and what drew me to him was not only his knowledge of Balthasar, but also his generous humanity. I will follow someone a long way if I think they care about others, and I will follow them even if it takes me longer than that to understand what they think. I remember puzzling over Steve’s Protestant instincts, uncertain how to gauge them, and yet dead certain he had put his heart into what he thought. This eventually opened me to understanding those instincts, and helped me welcome those instincts as embraceable by Catholic hearts too.

      This is a smaller example of what Steve’s book tries to uncover in the friendship between Balthasar and Barth, and what conversation refers to here. I think now of Balthasar’s theology of saints, which was for him a way to articulate the theology that they lived in the flesh. Barth, perhaps, would be another of Balthasar’s saints. Underneath Barth’s stubborn focus on Christ – which in Catholic eyes threatened to swallow the world whole – Balthasar saw love for Christ, a love that Balthasar worked to imitate in his own theology. This helps me to perceive more “warmth” in Barth than I might otherwise, and – as academic as he remains – I wonder if that is a failure to fully encounter the heart of his work. It may well be that Balthasar wanted to preserve and highlight that heart through his own work.

      Thank you, both, for such wonderful thoughts and great hope.

Avatar

Response

Reclaiming the Christological Center: D. Stephen Long on Christ, Ecumenism, and Theological Friendship

Some years ago I began to observe an interesting phenomenon at meetings of the Karl Barth Society of North America, usually held in conjunction with the AAR/SBL annual meeting. Increasingly these events were populated by younger evangelicals, some studying at traditional evangelical bastions like Wheaton and Baylor, others at Duke or Yale or Marquette. Moreover, these young scholars often seemed as conversant with Barth’s friend and conversation partner, Hans Urs von Balthasar, as with Barth himself. I recall well the occasion when a Barth society panel featured a much-heralded book by a conservative Roman Catholic who was highly critical of Balthasar. I was bemused to observe the evangelicals rushing to the defense of the great Catholic kenoticist. I recall thinking to myself, “these are interesting theological times.”

That evangelicals should find Barth’s theology so attractive might have been a surprise to Carl Henry or John Stott, although perhaps less so in Stott’s case; it was in America that Barth was often seen as dangerously “liberal.” That they should find Balthasar attractive would likely have been shocking. Yet in hindsight, we can see why this might have been so. Barth’s theology offers a powerful array of resources not only for evangelicals, but also for Protestants more generally, to confess Jesus Christ with boldness while avoiding a reactionary stance toward modernity. Barth allows one to be “orthodox and modern,” as Bruce McCormack put it. What Balthasar represents, even more so than Barth, is an opening toward the ancient church, the Fathers and yes, even the medieval scholastics, that seems increasingly compelling in face of a Protestant church life that seems ahistorical and lacking in ontic depth. When I was in graduate school in the 1980s, the reading of Aquinas by Protestants still seemed edgy and avant-garde; today nobody thinks twice about it. Astonishing commonplaces like these should be taken into account whenever people talk of an “ecumenical winter.”

We should not assume that developments like the ones I have been describing are inevitable, the result simply of sociological forces or of some murky Hegelian convergence. Individual historical agents matter. At least part of the credit for the renewed possibility of Catholic-evangelical encounter can be traced to the two men I have already been discussing. In the early 1940s Karl Barth and Hans Urs von Balthasar struck up a strange friendship in Basel, and the theological world has never quite been the same. D. Stephen Long’s Saving Karl Barth: Hans Urs von Balthasar’s Preoccupation is devoted to that friendship and its long-term significance for the churches today. It is a carefully argued book, but also a passionate one. As Balthasar wrote about Barth, “He is passionately enthusiastic about the subject matter of theology, but he is impartial in the way he approaches so volatile a subject. Impartiality means being plunged into the object, the very definition of objectivity” (89). Much the same could be said about Long’s writing.

In the opening chapter of the work, Long does a wonderful job of describing the complexities of Barth’s and Balthasar’s friendship. If overly detailed at times, the material will nevertheless be useful to future scholars. One of the things we learn is the price Balthasar paid for his “preoccupation” with Barth. In the 1940s he experienced constant difficulties with his ecclesiastical superiors, delaying the appearance of The Theology of Karl Barth by a decade. Balthasar’s loyalty to Barth is all the more admirable given the latter’s habit of making harsh pronouncements about Catholicism. As late as 1954 he said to a Protestant audience that no “decent person” could become a Roman Catholic. In the 1960s his mind changed again, as he approved the Catholic ressourcement associated with Balthasar, de Lubac, and a whole generation of younger Catholics. In 1966 he travelled to Rome to confer with many of the fathers of the Second Vatican Council. His critically sympathetic reading of major conciliar documents is to be found in Ad Limina Apostolorum, a work that deserves to be better known, in which he expressed the worry that Catholics might simply be treading the accomodationist path of modernist Protestantism. It was a worry that Balthasar would come to share.

This is, make no mistake, a book of advocacy. Despite the ecumenical advances I spoke of earlier, Long is worried that we are entering a new period of confessional retrenchment or even identity politics in the churches. A generation of younger Catholics seeks to retrieve the thought of nineteenth century Neo-Scholasticism, shocking their elders, who had thought they had said good-bye to all that at Vatican II. Meanwhile an influential school of Barth-interpretation is seeking to overthrow the idea that Barth made a “break with liberalism” or that he ever moved “from dialectic to theology.” Barth was a consistently dialectical thinker, according to McCormack and his allies. Just so he was theologically a modern—a critical modern, yes, but then criticism is what modernity is about. In this respect Barth has far more in common with Schleiermacher than with Aquinas, or at least with Aquinas as interpreted in a certain way. The important thing on this reading of Barth is that he tried to do serious Christian theology “under the conditions of modernity.” Those conditions are post-metaphysical, as the radical Barthians never cease to remind us. Their diagnosis agrees perfectly with that of the neo-neo-Thomists, except that the latter view modernity’s loss of metaphysics as nothing less than a disaster.

The situation just outlined sets out the agenda for Long’s project: recovering what Barth and Balthasar thought they had discovered, what drew them together despite all their differences (never fully resolved) over particular theological issues. What drew them together was Jesus Christ. More precisely, the terrain Long seeks to recover in this book is that of a comprehensive Christocentric view of reality, encompassing the divine and the human, nature and grace, doctrine and ethics. Though in very different forms, such a vision is embodied both in Barth’s Church Dogmatics and in Balthasar’s The Glory of the Lord. Long is frankly puzzled that anyone would want to reject this vision, either by returning to a static theology built on “pure nature” (the Thomist option) or by rejecting metaphysics altogether in favor of a kind of historicism (the radical Barthians). Long’s project, in brief, is to find a via media between these extremes.

Or should we say a via dialectica? An interesting feature of Long’s method is that he essentially adapts Barth’s procedure in Church Dogmatics 1.1 of navigating between competing “heresies.” In that volume, the heresies in question are identified as Roman Catholicism and liberal Protestantism. Both silence the Word in favor of human certainties, whether the ecclesial magisterium or modernity’s rational/experiential subject. Long keeps the method but changes the players. He replaces Catholicism with neo-Thomism and liberal Protestantism with radical Barthianism. The desired space in between is Barth as Balthasar would like to have read him—a theologian in the Reformation tradition, to be sure, yet one whose evangelicalism affirms Catholicism’s fundamental commitment to the created order. To be sure, nature is to be understood only retrospectively, in light of the economy of salvation. Here Long decisively parts company with the contemporary neo-scholastics. On Long’s reading, Barth’s polemic against the analogy of being was misguided, because he himself had shown just how far it is true that Christ is the Alpha and the Omega, the beginning and end of all things. Hence there is nothing in all creation that is not oriented toward him, nothing whose “nature” is not fulfilled in “grace.” For Long as for Balthasar, the difference between Barth’s analogia fidei and this Christological version of the analogia entis is so small as to be negligible.

A major subplot of the book is theology’s conditions of possibility. Both the neo-scholastics and the radical Barthians are confident that they are serving the interests of the economy of grace, by ensuring that it is connected to “reality.” For the Thomists, reality means pure nature; for the Barthians, it means an act of election whose historical character must be brought into the very heart of the Trinity. The one school is metaphysical, the other anti-metaphysical, but both share a characteristic modern concern for rational clarity. While Long has a high respect for the work of philosophers, as a theologian he shares what George Hunsinger has called Barth’s “high tolerance for mystery,” and is therefore suspicious of attempts to reduce the complex harmonies of theology to a rationalist monotone. (In true Barthian and Balthasarian fashion, the book abounds in musical metaphors.) Christ must not be sacrificed on the altar of philosophical systems. Or for that matter, on the altar of theological politics: at several points, Long suggests that his opponents’ views are too much shaped by church-political interests. For the neo-scholastics, claims about pure nature lead directly to claims about the ordering of society: if we know with clarity what human nature is, why not enshrine it in law? (96–98). For the radical Barthians, an actualistic doctrine of election serves the interests of Reformed identity, giving a demoralized Protestantism something to be “about” (111; this is my formulation, but I think Long would agree). Of course, such criticisms can always be directed back at the one who makes them. Are evangelical Catholics like Long (and myself) so deeply committed to the cause of Christian unity—talk about demoralized!—that we have become suspiciously “soft on truth”? Perhaps. The via media is not only a difficult way, but may be the way of self-deception. Thus Barth’s ambivalent attitude toward ecumenism. He feared that a rush toward the middle might compromise the singularity of Jesus Christ, “the one Word of God whom we have to hear, and whom we have to trust and obey in life and in death,” in the words of the Barmen Declaration.

Barth famously confessed that if he were forced to choose between the evils of Roman Catholicism and modernist Protestantism he would unhesitatingly choose the former; of course he did not believe any such choice was necessary. There is a similar revealing moment in Long’s book. In the course of discussing Kevin Hector’s Theology without Metaphysics, a “therapy” aimed at helping us overcome metaphysical nostalgia, Long admits that if “forced to choose between [the neo-Thomists’] version of Thomism and Hector’s therapy, I would tend toward Hector’s therapy” (169). Why is that? Long does not tell us in so many words. The impression he conveys, though, is that while Hector may have conceded far too much to Heidegger in his effort to speak of God, it is nevertheless God—the triune God!—he intends to speak of. Whereas in the case of the neo-Thomists, the doctrine of pure nature requires the positing of a putative realm “outside” Christ, which must then laboriously be related to him: Christ as theological afterthought. It should be noted that Long does not think the problem lies with Aquinas himself, who, as Balthasar well knew, can be read in a way such that theology clearly takes the lead over metaphysics. Among the neo-Thomists only Thomas Joseph White seems to catch a glimmer of this, and Long’s criticisms of him are accordingly far more measured.

The danger Long courts in all of this is allowing his opponents to dictate the terms of the debate. The point of overcoming the misreadings of Barth and Balthasar, after all, is not to perpetuate the contemporary metaphysics wars, but to retrieve their particular way of doing theology—talk about God. While Long can do scholastic theology with the best of them, it is in the book’s later chapters, devoted to the material loci God-ethics-ecclesiology, that he really shines. Of the making of books on Barth’s ethics there seems to be no end—rather surprising, given the severe criticisms to which it has been subject—yet Long’s retracing of this familiar ground is fresh and full of insight. A key ecumenical question emerges at this point: to what extent is the Christian ethical subject an “ecclesial subject”? Barth’s and Balthasar’s sensibilities are quite different here, with Barth subjecting the Christian directly to the command of God by virtue of his or her election, and Balthasar envisioning hierarchical vocations within the one body of Christ (laity, clergy, religious, etc.). Taking Balthasar’s side in these debates, Long raises the question whether the mature Barth’s understanding of the human subject doesn’t in the end float above history, just to the extent that it fails to make room for the church: “If the church as Christ’s body is not extended in time, creation loses its purpose. It becomes void of theological significance. For Balthasar, in opposition to Barth, creation has different gradations of proximity to the Christological center” (230).

These are very big claims—too big to address adequately in this review. I will simply press one point. First, granted that Barth was wrong about sacramental mediation—I agree with Long on this—does this mean he was also wrong to reject the notion of the church as “prolongation of the incarnation”? How does Long’s advocacy of this notion comport with his acknowledgment that “Barth’s laudable concern is to avoid identifying Jesus’ unique hypostatic union with the church and produce an ecclesial triumphalism”? (215). For that matter, I wonder how characteristic the “prolongation” idea is even of Balthasar. Long adduces a single quotation where Balthasar states: “The Church is the prolongation of Christ’s mediatorial nature and work and possesses a knowledge that comes by faith” (230). Yet if by faith, any sense of “prolongation” must be strongly qualified. To this one would have to add Balthasar’s construal of the church in terms of Mary—precisely an “other” to Christ—and his theology of the church as “chaste whore.” In general, the prolongation-idea seems a clumsy and, as Long himself notes, potentially disastrous way of affirming the totus Christus.

The chapter on ecclesiology proper, however, is my favorite (chapter 6, “The Realm of the Church: Renewal and Unity”). This is where Long takes us inside Barth’s 1941 seminar on the Council of Trent, focused on the sacraments, and at which Balthasar was present. The fact that we have detailed student protocols of this seminar makes it possible to reconstruct the give and take of theological argument. This encounter was anything but an irenic rush toward the middle. Barth and his students asked whether there is any role for faith in Catholic sacramental teaching, given the emphasis on sacraments as “causes” of grace—ex opere operato—while for his part Balthasar asked why secondary causes should be seen as detracting from God’s glory: “Is it irksome for Rembrandt to use a brush?” (256). Balthasar’s strong affirmation of the personal, appropriative force of the sacraments, as well as their sign-character, certainly gave the Protestants a great deal to think about. The participants in the seminar did not claim to have resolved all the confessional differences. What is striking, however, is the extent to which popular perceptions of Catholic and Protestant sacramental teaching, and even some scholarly accounts, still have not risen to the level of understanding Barth and Balthasar achieved in 1941. Clearly there is a great deal of ecumenical work still to be done.

This is a necessary book for our theological moment. Although I have dwelt on its polemical features—and the polemics are indeed integral to the argument—it would be unfortunate if the book were seen mainly as being “against” certain positions. As in the work of both his authors, the Nein stands in service of the Ja—God’s great “Yes” to humanity in Jesus Christ. But to live from Christ means participating in the passion to which he, the Son of God, freely subjected himself on our behalf. Early in the book, Long comments that from his theological beginnings “Barth chose, in his words, to ‘suffer’ Catholicism. It was a worthy adversary. But if Barth suffered Catholicism, Balthasar returned the favor” (14). As Long well documents, Balthasar literally suffered a certain alienation from his own communion because of his odd preoccupation with the Reformed theologian from Basel. Without valorizing or sentimentalizing these thinkers, who were certainly not without their faults, we may perhaps see them as figures for our divided churches. Both tried to live and think from the center—not a cheap middle way, but Christ the Center. Both lived from the incarnation and cross to such an extent that they could confront each other non-defensively and even joyfully. Not accidentally, their theological encounter took the form of friendship, which means spending time with the other, literally “suffering” his or her presence for Christ’s sake. It would be a fine thing if Saving Karl Barth became an occasion for more such friendships.

  • D. Stephen Long

    D. Stephen Long

    Reply

    Response to Joseph Mangina

    Joseph Mangina raises several insightful questions about my book. Let me focus on two. The first is whether the polemical edge of my book led me astray by letting my interlocutors set my agenda. The second has to do with a question George Hunsinger raised as well. Have I sided too thoroughly with Balthasar and/or a Catholic interpretation of the church as an extension of the incarnation? Moreover, is this a central teaching in Balthasar or Catholicism after Vatican II? I appreciate both questions, though answering them is not easy. Let me address them in order.

    I did not want my defense of Balthasar’s reading of Barth against either the postmetaphysical Barthians or the neoscholastics to be the focus of the book. I began working on the book before I came to realize where these two theological positions were headed. In fact, the book did not begin as a defense of Balthasar’s reading of Barth against anything, but simply as a continuation of an earlier work, Speaking of God: Theology, Language and Truth. (That book would also be my answer to Mangina’s important question, “Are evangelical Catholics like Long (and myself) so deeply committed to the cause of Christian unity . . . that we have become suspiciously ‘soft on truth’?”) In that earlier work, I tried to challenge an either-or I saw in modern theology, Catholic and Protestant, that set philosophy over and against theology, reason over and against faith, and nature over and against grace. These binaries seem to me too dialectical and not at the heart of either good philosophy or theology. Both Balthasar and Barth’s use of analogy challenge these dialectical divisions. Speaking of God began with two quotes. First was Barth’s: “The greatest temptation and danger consists in this, that the theologian will actually becomes what he seems to be—a philosopher.” Second was Balthasar’s: “without philosophy there can be no theology.” In what could be seen as a contradiction, I affirmed both positions and attempted to argue that Barth and Balthasar’s Christological analogy brought the two positions closer together than it might on the surface seem. I knew at the time that more needed to be said; Saving Karl Barth was that more.

    I was only vaguely aware at that time (prior to 2009) that some Catholic theologians were recovering neoscholasticism in an attempt to challenge modernity. The more I became aware of this challenge, the more it seemed to me to repeat modernity by accepting the above binaries; reason or philosophy became a foundation for theology. This reason was based on a pure nature that allowed for “metaphysical objectivity” without which theology could not be properly done. Metaphysics conditions theology. It is the answer to historicism, a putatively modern error as if no one prior to Kant or Dilthey was aware of history (see Speaking of God, 72). Nor was I fully aware of the consequences of the postmetaphysical reading of Barth by some Protestant theologians where the historicization of being was necessary because of modernity. I had read and appreciated much of Robert Jenson’s work, although I wondered about his critique of divine simplicity—a teaching Barth affirmed. Like many others I gained immense knowledge from McCormack’s Karl Barth’s Critically Realistic Dialectical Theology. I wondered about his interpretation of Balthasar and the marginalization of Barth’s Anselm book, but I did not know enough of the history when I first read it to offer any learned alternative. I was surprised by the direction he took Barth in Orthodox and Modern: Studies in the Theology of Barth and by the direction he took theology in his “Election and Trinity.” Although my original impetus for saying more about how Barth and Balthasar can be brought together came from the inadequacy of Speaking of God, perhaps I let the polemics of chapter three set too much of the tone for the work? As I read more of these two schools of thought, it appeared to me that they worked well against each other. The difficulty with polemics is they tend to be reactive such that you need what you react against in order for your argument to work. I hope my argument works even if I have misread the postmetaphysical Barthians or the ressourcement Thomists. I hope they will engage the work and let us know if I have. (Robert Jenson responds to it in a forthcoming issue of Pro Ecclesia.) There is much to affirm in both those theologies so if they found that I have fit them into a structure that fits my argument and not theirs, I hope that will not take away from the heart of my argument about the importance of Barth and Balthasar’s theological conversation for how we speak of God, ethics and the church. Nonetheless, Mangina is correct when he calls my work a “book of advocacy” that worries about “a new period of confessional retrenchment.”

    Mangina also rightly notes one source of my worry: “For the neo-scholastics, claims about pure nature lead directly to claims about the ordering of society: if we know with clarity what human nature is, why not enshrine it in law? (96–98). For the radical Barthians, an actualistic doctrine of election serves the interests of Reformed identity, giving a demoralized Protestantism something to be “about” (111; this is my formulation, but I think Long would agree).” I do indeed agree.

    The second question he raises is about ecclesiology. He describes my argument well. I affirm both the reason behind Barth’s rejection of the church as the extension of the incarnation. It avoids ecclesial triumphalism and absorbing Jesus into his church, and for Balthasar’s affirmation of the teaching it allows for the theodrama to unfold in history with real agents whose free actions matter. These affirmations could be an example of Magina’s concern that the desire for unity by evangelical Catholics like us makes us soft on truth. Does this teaching not set an either-or before us? Should the logic of non-contradiction cause one side or the other to say, “Here I stand. I can do no other?” Someone will have to be correct and someone wrong? I confess I do not tend to find such either-or positions adequate. They tend toward dialectical or univocal theologies when what we need is analogy. It is why I criticized Brad Gregory’s Unintended Reformation when he renders the enigmatic rupture between Catholics and Protestants reasonable by saying the polemics of the sixteenth century “simply reflected a clear understanding on all sides of the logical necessity that contrary truth claims cannot all be true” (244). One legacy from the debacles of the sixteenth century, it seems to me, is that clarity of vision often escapes us. There is truth, and then there is the appearance of truth. Everyone always assumes what he or she is saying and doing is true, unless he or she is intentionally deceptive. Truth is, as Aquinas noted, a transcendental predicate of being. It is inescapable, which does not mean its appearance to us is without significant errors. Those errors are more difficult to see than the inevitability of truth, and this is why the question of truth is so difficult. There are interpretations of the church as the extension of the incarnation that could pose a dialectical either-or. If the argument were that because the church is the extension of the incarnation, it could not be reformed, then we would have such an either-or. We would have to choose between semper Reformanda and an infallible church incapable of reform. Did such an interpretation ever exist on the Catholic side? Both Trent and Vatican II would seem to suggest otherwise. Vatican II did affirm the teaching of the church as the extension of the incarnation by using the vague expression “by no weak analogy” the church “is compared to the mystery of the incarnate Word.” Is that objectionable? Must the Reformed side assume everything must always be in error and thus subject to revision? That leads to the indefensible “Protestant Principle” of Tillich, a principle that is a performative contradiction because it cannot itself be reformed.

    I confess I struggled with this section (218–38) more than any other and worried I had betrayed the better insights of the Reformation. I rewrote it more than any other section in the book. I also consulted friends and other scholars at length. Conversations with Kimlyn Bender over his Karl Barth’s Christological Ecclesiology were immensely helpful, although I did not finally come down precisely where he does. He helped me see why the discussion was so important. I received so many mixed answers from Catholic friends on whether or not the Roman Catholic Church still taught the church is a “prolongation of the incarnation” that I was, and am, confused as to how to interpret Lumen gentium. However, Bill Cavanaugh’s essay, “The Sinfulness and Visibility of the Church: A Christological Exploration,” in his Migrations of the Holy was immensely clarifying. It finally convinced me that I could affirm both Barth’s rightful worry about ecclesial triumphalism and the need for the Catholic teaching for it insists on the necessity of the visible church as the site for theodramatic action. If the church is not in some real sense the body of Christ, which is of course Scripture’s witness, then our Christianity will become “gnostic.” The corporate body of Christ will lack embodiment in the world and be dissolved into an invisible church that only the enlightened can see. Cavanaugh, drawing on Balthasar’s important essay, “Casa Meretrix” (The Chaste Prostitute), develops a version of the Catholic teaching that I did not think would be objectionable to Reformed theologians. I did not sufficiently exegete it, but that essay mentioned on pages 218–19 is the reason I affirmed Balthasar on page 230 without assuming I had betrayed Barth. I could be wrong. If the Catholic hierarchy would ever claim that its institutional structure is beyond reform, I would be. My hope is that Catholics and Protestants would examine Cavanaugh’s defense of the teaching of the church as an extension of the incarnation to see if we cannot gain some clarity on one apparent reason for the enigmatic rupture among us—a rupture that seems to be as much among Catholics as between Catholics and Protestants.

Kenneth Oakes

Response

On Being Modern, a Methodist, and the Analogy of Being

It seems strange to call a former mentor and current friend “Long,” so at the costs of seeming insubordinate I’ll refer to the author of Saving Karl Barth as “Steve.” As a longer review of Steve’s remarkable book will be forthcoming elsewhere,1 the following will consist mainly of observations followed by questions and will be informal in tone. I realize that this interrogative format puts additional burdens of time and energy upon Steve, but it’s too difficult to avoid the temptation of indulging my curiosity and yet again “raising my hand” to ask a past and present teacher some questions. I would, then, be happy with simply vague or general impressions.

On Being Modern

“Being modern” is said in many ways. The list of scholars who read Karl Barth as modern is long and varied and for each scholar handles Barth’s “being modern” in different ways. Ingrid Spieckermann and Bruce McCormack have focused on modern epistemological inheritances, Trutz Rendtorff and Gerald McKenny on modern ethical commitments (particularly that of autonomy), while others have seen Barth’s “being modern” in the context of his theological decisions within his doctrine of Scripture; his revisions of the doctrines of election and divine simplicity and impassibility; his stress that God’s being is always a free and loving being-in-act; his distinction between Historie and Geschichte and his use of Saga; his deeply respectful yet judicious listening to traditional Protestant creeds and confessions; his wariness to natural theology in both theological and political forms, and the list could go on. While these modern commitments irreducibly shape and inform Barth’s theology, they do not exhaust it. Equally, some of these commitments figure more prominently in Barth’s theology while others play a fairly minor role. It is also clear that Barth can often ignore, excoriate, or run roughshod over the concerns of modern theology, and thankfully so.

Given that Steve is attempting to pushback against a line of Barth interpretation that he sees rendering Barth a modern, postmetaphysical, and ecumenically limited theology, it makes sense that Barth’s modern inheritances are not addressed at length and that Barth is often seen as overcoming the problems of modernity. For instance, in a passage dealing with readings of Barth’s doctrine of God, Steve can write, “By providing an alternative to the deus absconditus, Barth poses a challenge to a core thesis of modern theology. Barth is not a modern theologian, but one who provides a doctrine of God to heal a modern theology that too often confused the Christian God with Isis” (154). I would, however, see no contradiction in stating that Barth is an irreducibly yet not slavish modern theologian who could overcome one problem within modern theology (or better put, a problem within some doctrines of God since the Late Medieval Period) while nevertheless remaining modern in many other ways.

My question to Steve, then, is what he would make of Barth’s modern inheritances and whether he thinks it helpful or distracting to focus on or develop them. If this question is too broad or unclear, then perhaps a more focused question could be addressed: what is Steve’s understanding of the role of Kantian or critical philosophy, either in its practical or theoretical forms, in Barth’s work. While it is a tiresome question, it is still commonly misunderstood by being either overestimated or underappreciated.

On Being Methodist

While Steve is an ordained Methodist elder, his instincts and views on various issues can run the theological gambit: from approaching the Roman Catholic to nearing the Anabaptist. Nevertheless, as so richly portrayed in a recent article for The Christian Century,2 the Methodists are those folk who have guided him and given to him, and they are the same folk who in turn keep asking him to do things. Throughout the book Steve can both appreciate and blast the “postmetaphysical Barthians” and the “Ressourcement Thomists,” even admitting at one point that he would choose the former if forced to decide. Yet in the second, more doctrinal half of the book, one gains the impression that Steve feels more at home in von Balthasar’s roomy, Christocentric Catholicism than in Barth’s equally roomy (though it may not appear so at times), Christocentric Protestantism. Perhaps this impression is merely a misimpression, but my question to Steve would be whether his time with the Methodists has tilted his hand towards von Balthasar. One could imagine Wesleyan intuitions on sanctification and holiness, prevenience grace, communal discipleship, constant communion, catholicity, the intimate relationship between doctrine and life, etc., as providing just such an impetus for generally leaning towards von Balthasar. If being Methodist is in fact not such an impetus, I would be grateful to hear a bit more about this apparent leaning more towards von Balthasar than to Barth.

On the Analogy of Being

In the course of posing some questions to the Ressourcement Thomists regarding metaphysics and the intelligibility of the incarnation, Steve offers the following:

“If this conditioning of revelation is correct, then to put it whimsically, we will need to correct Scripture. Jesus would have to counter Thomas’s confession in John 20:28, ‘My Lord and my God,’ without something like, ‘Well I know you think you know what this means, but you cannot make this confession properly until you become aware it is conditioned by the analogia entis found in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics taken up by the Thomist manual tradition after the thirteen century’”3 (169).

The above passage comes from a section entitled “What is at stake in the analogia entis?” While Steve levels criticisms at any account of the analogy of being which views it as a metaphysical framework which conditions revelation, as well as criticisms at those who attempt to circumvent metaphysics pragmatically, the reader is still left with what Steve himself thinks is at stake. Generally speaking, Steve seems well-disposed towards the analogy of being as promoted by von Balthasar (and perhaps by Przywara), and yet it would be good to hear more of what Steve thinks about the use of the analogy of being within theology, particularly within the context of Christology as raised in the passage above. I realize that entire monographs have been dedicated to these issues, but I would be grateful to hear Steve think out loud.

 


  1. Pro Ecclesia, forthcoming.

  2. D. Stephen Long, ‘Why I am Not Yet a Catholic’, The Christian Century (Jul 28, 2014).

  3. Thankfully Jesus’ answer to Thomas is “Because you have seen me, you have believed; blessed are those who have not seen and yet have believed.”

  • D. Stephen Long

    D. Stephen Long

    Reply

    Response to Kenneth Oakes

    Ken Oakes honors me by suggesting he was and is my student. Would that I could take more responsibility for his work as a theologian. His Karl Barth on Philosophy and Theology should put an end to facile criticisms of Barth that suggest Barth had no time for philosophy. In fact, it helps me make my case for putting Barth and Balthasar together as I mentioned in my previous response to Joe Mangina. Barth’s worry that theologians might become nothing more than philosophers was never meant to convey that philosophy has no role to play in theology. The first question Ken puts to me is the question as to what that role is. Have I given sufficient attention to the fact that Barth was in many ways engaged with modern philosophy and theology, especially Kant? In response to my assertion that Barth challenges a “core thesis of modern theology” Ken states his own position nicely: “I would, however, see no contradiction in stating that Barth is an irreducibly yet not slavish modern theologian who could overcome one problem within modern theology (or better put, a problem within some doctrines of God since the Late Medieval Period) while nevertheless remaining modern in many other ways.” I’m not sure we have a significant difference here, but let me address his concern to see if we do.

    The question Ken rightly raises is if the term “modernity” does too much for me. I looked at my use of the term and noticed how often I use the expression that some Barthians set Barth “within modernity.” Of course, every theologian writing today is in some sense “modern.” We all work with philosophical and cultural assumptions and practices not present before the seventeenth century. Both Barth and Balthasar are, in that sense, modern theologians; they use and address those philosophical and cultural assumptions. I argued that for both of them there was a “crisis of modernity,” and that neither were reactionary imagining that the proper response is to eschew modernity and retrieve something pure called “pre-modernity.” The distinctions between these epochs can be both overdrawn and underestimated. When a putative premodern “substance” metaphysics is set against a modern emphasis on history, then I think the distinction is overdrawn. But there are some “modern” emphases that enable us to distinguish it from the “pre-modern.” My use of the term “modernity” draws upon four: a privileging of epistemology over ontology; ethics as first philosophy turning theology into a “practical” rather than a speculative discipline; the cultural assumption that assumes “relevance”—the new and improved—must drive theological work; and a doctrine of God that so emphasizes God as sovereign will it loses the relationship between divine goodness and truth. Let me examine each briefly.

    The first is philosophical. As Louis Dupré and others have argued the modern era places an emphasis on epistemology over and against ontology. How we can know what we know becomes more important than what we know. This emphasis leads to a preoccupation with method. If I challenge a “modern” interpretation of Barth, it is primarily challenging this emphasis. The “modern” interpretation assumes Balthasar lacked a full understanding of Barth because he did not take into account the Göttingen Dogmatics, especially chapter 15, and its emphasis on a Kantian epistemology. Barth does draw on Kant’s phenomenal/noumenal distinction in that chapter, but he also emphasizes that the fact philosophy cannot give us direct knowledge of God is nothing new. He cites Aristotle and Aquinas as teaching something similar. If that is the case, then how “modern” could Barth be? He seems to read Kant in terms of questions that arose prior to the modern epoch. As I shall argue below, Christopher Insole has argued that this is what drove Kant’s work.

    The second concern about modernity has to do with the conditions of theology; something Joseph Mangina noted as a central task in Saving Karl Barth. Ethics becomes “first philosophy” in much of modern theology. It becomes a practical rather than speculative exercise. This too, of course, has its foundation in Kant’s moral proof for the existence of God in his second critique; something Barth never affirmed. Barth’s early essays, especially the 1916 “Righteousness of Faith,” acknowledged that “ethics” cannot be our first philosophy. Rather than ethics providing access to God, ethics only makes sense once God’s triune agency is set forth. Here Barth seems to me to be more like Aquinas than Kant. As Aquinas noted theology is first speculative and then practical because practical reason focuses on the contingent and the made. God is neither. Theology is only practical when it refers to creation’s relation to God, which is an essential task in theology, but this does not mean we must begin there and eschew speculative knowledge of God. Barth’s Church Dogmatics II.1 had the boldness of a speculative knowledge of God; it does not use “ethics” as a gateway to our knowledge of God.

    These first two uses of the term “modernity” can easily trace their lineage to Kant. It overstates the matter to suggest Kant was post-metaphysical. If one follows Christopher Insole’s important argument in his Kant and the Creation of Freedom, then Kant’s affirmation of noumenal causation as a ground for freedom is clearly metaphysical. If there is such causation, then it may entail we cannot provide a “theory” about it for our theories are intelligible in terms of immanent causal laws. Noumenal causation interrupts those laws and reminds us of the importance of the mystery of our own freedom. This raises the question how Kant could have access to “noumenal causation,” and his answer seems to be through practical reason, through ethics. As Insole notes, Kant’s theology lacks any doctrine of the Trinity, any first philosophy other than ethics, and a participatory metaphysics. Kant was concerned with Medieval theological themes, but his answers were modern. Insole states it well in the main theme of his work, “Kant struggles with a problem that is irreducibly theological: how can it be said that human beings are free, given that they are created by God?” Kant’s question is not new; his answers emphasize epistemology and ethics as first philosophy. When I stated that some Barthians are reading Barth “within modernity,” I meant within these two emphases. I think this overstates the influence of Kant on Barth and overlooks what Balthasar saw in his work; Barth is not concerned with making theology modern by emphasizing epistemology or turning theological into a practical, ethical discipline.

    Barth’s criticism of Vatican II’s aggiornamento, his simple question “updating to what?,” shows how unconcerned he was to be “relevant” to some modern era. If the modern is understood as a twofold trajectory where everything we have known or done up to this point is obsolete because it cannot prepare us for the “new” that is about to arrive but never does, and we must discard it for the sake of relevance, then Barth was unconcerned with being modern. It did not preoccupy him. I also argued that Barth’s explicit critique of nominalism, coupled with his reading the de deo uno within the de deo trino is what Balthasar learned from him more than anything else. This reading of God’s unity (simplicity, impassibility, eternity, etc.) within the triune Persons is a retrieval of an option not taken either by neoscholasticism or liberal Protestantism, both of which assume too sharp a modern distinction between faith and reason. These four concerns are why I would see Barth as not preoccupied with modernity. I did not argue he seeks to be some kind of conservative reactionary who defends some epoch prior to modernity. Whenever I am tempted to be too romantic about critiques of modernity, my good colleague Ulrich Lehner reminds me of “modern dentistry.” He is correct. In fact, as an avid cyclist I recognize that “progress” begins with the autonomous movement the bicycle created. I would like to write a work in defense of modernity that looks at material practices like the bicycle. “Modernity,” whatever it is, is not something one simply accepts or rejects. If I suggested as much, Ken is correct to challenge it.

    Ken also asks whether my “time with the Methodists has tilted [my] hand towards von Balthasar.” That is possible, but I’m unsure because I am unclear as to what it means to be a “Methodist theologian.” I think my work, for better or worse, was more marked by the “evangelical Catholicism” I learned from Duke than it was by Methodism per se. I have never found a vocation as a “Methodist theologian” because I do not think such a vocation exists. In fact, I do not read Barth primarily as a Reformed or Protestant theologian. I read him as a “catholic” theologian; I think he could be a “common doctor” for the church catholic, although he may not have embodied the sanctity necessary for such a role. I would never claim that mantle for my own work; I know it is at best a footnote to the work of others, but I do try to write for a “catholic” church that does not yet exist. I try to be a catholic theologian. This desire more so than being a Methodist theologian is the reason for my effort to bring Barth and Balthasar into conversation.

    Finally Ken states, “it would be good to hear more of what Steve think about the use of the analogy of being within theology, particularly within the context of Christology as raised in the passage above.” The passage to which he refers is my “whimsical” critique of some accounts of the analogy of being that suggest the incarnation would be unintelligible without it. That suggestion could have a strong or weak version. The strong version argues that Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and a metaphysics of act/potency are the necessary condition for recognizing the incarnation. Such a position is absurd. It cannot make sense of the disciple Thomas’s confession in the Gospel of John or any of the biblical witnesses that acknowledge Jesus is God and bowed the knee to him. Must they have read Aristotle for their witness to be reasonable? A weaker version of it suggests nothing more than the fact that because God became incarnate in Jesus, human nature must be able to receive divinity without ceasing to be humanity. The two become one without confusing humanity and divinity. This tells us something about “being.” I do not think I need to say more than that about the analogia entis, which is why I wrote, “If the analogia entis is nothing more than the obvious fact that because God was incarnate in Christ, divinity and humanity exist in some kind of natural intelligibility, then it should be noncontroversial. Balthasar affirmed it, as did Barth implicitly, when he develops his doctrine of creation as the external basis for covenant and covenant as the internal basis for creation.” Barth has what I take to be a clear statement of the analogia entis in his Doctrine of Reconciliation: “The royal man of the New Testament tradition is created ‘after God’ (κατα θεον). This means that as a man He exists analogously to the mode of existence of God” (Church Dogmatics IV.2, 166). How is this not a version of the analogia entis? Does Barth then want to deny that Jesus as “man” is human as others are human? That would be heretical. I would like to think that the analogia entis is noncontroversial. It should not be viewed as something that is church dividing. I would be interested in hearing how I am incorrect about an affirmation of this weaker version.

    • Avatar

      George Hunsinger

      Reply

      A Response to Kenneth Oakes and Steve Long

      Not every analogy would be an analogia entis. If the human Jesus exists, for Barth, analogously to the mode of God, then that is a pure (and ongoing) miracle. It has nothing to do with “being” as such, or with “pure nature,” or even with something called “graced nature.” Not even graced human nature can be enhanced to the point where it is analogous to the mode of God in itself and as such. All such analogies for Barth are grounded entirely in grace alone. They are therefore real but incomprehensible. They are, as he says, a matter of inconceivable similarities.

      The idea of an analogia entis, no matter what the form, wants to eliminate this element of sheer inconceivability. It wants to make the incomprehensible comprehensible and the miraculous element relative rather than absolute. The analogia relationis, however, for Barth, is a matter of absolute miracle, grounded entirely in the freedom of God. It has no secondary ground in created nature, whether “pure” or “graced” or otherwise. It is aways an ongoing miraculous event. The condition for its possibility lies entirely in God. There can be no analogia entis, because God and the creature are ontologically incommensurable.

    • Kenneth Oakes

      Kenneth Oakes

      Reply

      A Response to Steve Long and George Hunsinger

      Steve’s response was wonderfully illuminating, particularly as regards his commitment to a type of ‘evangelical Catholicism’. The reason why I asked about the analogy of being is that I’m still uncertain as to what to make of it, especially as regards Christology, and I was curious to hear some of Steve’s ideas. Currently I view the analogy of being, at least as put forward by Przywara, as a bundle of different decisions, some of which I find helpful and some of which find less helpful. (And Steve mentioned at least one of its uses in this response.) This is why I politely demur from Prof. Hunsinger’s claim that the analogy of being, ‘no matter what the form’, takes away from the ‘sheer inconceivability’ of God in and of himself. In fact, one of my worries about Przywara’s account of analogy as a ‘reductio in mysterium’ (and here I think that Jüngel would share the same worry) is that it could incline itself to an apophaticism of silence rather than a joyous, bold, and unequivocal proclamation that Jesus Christ reveals the triune God to be both freely and inherently for us and with us. The main goal of Przywara’s analogy of being is to ensure that the Creator-creature distinction always remains in effect, regardless of the doctrinal loci under discussion and regardless of the topic being address (which for a good portion of the Christian traditions includes the topic of ‘being’).

      If I’m reading Prof. Hunsinger’s comment correctly, then it also seems to raise the issue of creaturely analogues to God, a question which raises the longstanding discussion regarding communicable and incommunicable attributes. I think it salutary and necessary for theology to begin with Prof. Hunsinger’s question: which of the divine attributes could possibly be communicated to creatures? To which the answer should be: neither the ‘metaphysical’ attributes nor the ‘moral’. However, after this initial shock there comes the fact of the existence of creatures who are elected to be genuine covenant-partners with God, and to whom God gives ever afresh his righteousness, love, wisdom, and power (to invoke Luther’s Preface to the Latin Writings), perfections which are always alien to these covenant partners and yet aim at creating creatures who can in turn be genuine and free covenant-partners with God. As alien attributes, the condition for their possibility lie entirely in God, and even as creatio continua, and yet in Christ God gives to creatures the reality and possibility of being such covenant partners. Does one need the analogy of being to aid in such claim. Certainly not. And yet Przywara’s account of the analogy of being seems roomy enough to allow for such claims while one is still free to ignore some of its other elements.
Shares